CHAPTER IV.
On the Solicitude of the State for the Negative Welfare of the Citizen--For
His Security
To counteract the evil which arises from the tendency man has to transgress
his own appropriate limits,[1] and the discord occasioned by such unjust
encroachment on the rights of others, constitutes the essential ground
and object of State-union. If it were the same with these subversive manifestations
to which we allude, as with the physical violence of nature, or with the
working of that moral evil which disturbs the natural order of things through
excessive enjoyment or privation, or through other actions inconsistent
with that order—then would such unions no longer be necessary. The former,
or physical, evil would be encountered by the unaided efforts of human
courage, skill, and forethought: the latter, or moral, by the wisdom which
is matured in experience; and with either, in any case, the removal of
an evil would be the termination of a struggle. Under such a supposition,
therefore, any ultimate, absolute authority, such as properly constitutes
the idea of the State, would be wholly unneeded. But, as it is, human variance
and discord are utterly different in their nature from these, and positively
necessitate at all times the existence of some supreme power like that
to which we refer. For in this discordancy one conflict springs immediately
from another. Wrong begets revenge; and revenge is but a new wrong. And
hence it becomes necessary to look for some species of revenge which does
not admit of any other retaliation—that is the punishment inflicted by
the State, or for a settlement of the controversy which obliges the the
parties to rest satisfied, viz. the decision of the judge. There is nothing,
moreover, which necessitates such stringent coercion and such unconditional
obedience as man’s spirit of enterprise against his fellow-men, whether
we regard the expulsion of foreign enemies, or the preservation of security
within the State itself. Now, without security, it is impossible for man
either to develope his powers, or to enjoy the fruits of his exertion;
for, without security, there can be no freedom. But it will be seen at
once that this is a condition which man is wholly unable to realize by
his own individual efforts; the reasons we have just hinted at serve to
show this, and we are confirmed in the conviction by experience; for although
we observe that our States are in a far more favourable position than we
can conceive that of man in a state of nature to be (closely knit together,
as they are, by innumerable treaties and bonds of alliance, and by mutual
fear, which so constantly prevents the actual outbreaks of violence)—we
must allow, notwithstanding, that they do not possess that freedom which
under the most ordinary constitution the very meanest subject enjoys. Whilst,
therefore, I have hitherto found reasons for withdrawing the exercise of
State solicitude from many important objects, because the nation can accomplish
them as effectually and without incurring the evils which flow from State
interference, I must for similar reasons direct it to Security as to the
only thing[2] which the individual cannot obtain for himself and by his
own unaided efforts. I would therefore lay down as the first positive principle—a
principle to be more carefully defined and limited in the subsequent course
of inquiry—that the maintenance of security, as well with regard to the
attacks of foreign enemies as to the danger of internal discord, constitutes
the true end of the State, and must especially occupy its activity.
Hitherto I have attempted only to define this true end of the State
in a negative way, by showing that the latter should not, at least, extend
the sphere of its solicitude any further.
If we refer to the pages of history we only find additional confirmation
of the position we would establish, in the fact that the kings in all earlier
nations were in reality nothing more than leaders in war, and judges in
times of peace. I says, kings. For (if I may be pardoned this digression),
in those very periods in which men most fondly cherish the feeling of freedom—possessing,
as they do, but little property, and only knowing and prizing personal
force, and placing the highest enjoyment in its exercise—in those very
periods, however strange it may seem, history shows us nothing but kings
and monarchies. We observe this in all the Asiatic political unions, in
those of the earliest ages of Greece, of Italy, and of those tribes who
loved freedom more devotedly than all—the German.[3] If we examine into
the reasons for this seeming contradiction, we are struck with the truth,
that the very choice of a monarchy is a proof that those who select that
form of government are in the enjoyment of the highest freedom. The idea
of a chief ruler arises only, as was before observed, from the deep-felt
necessity for some military leader and umpire of disputes. Now to have
one general or umpire is unquestionably the happiest provision for such
a necessity. The apprehension that the one person so selected may ultimately
become a master is unknown to the man who is truly free; he does not even
dream of such a possibility; to no one does he attribute the power of subjugating
his liberty, and to no one that is himself free the wish to lord it over
others—for he who is utterly insensible to the sublime beauty of liberty
and thirsts only for dominion, is in reality in love with slavery, so long
as he does not contemplate the likelihood of being himself a slave; and
thus it is, that as the science of morals originated in crime, and theology
in heresy, so politics sprang into existence with servitude.
And yet, although we find their prototypes in antiquity, it is certain
that our monarchs have not the honeyed and persuasive speech which characterized
the kings of Homer and Hesiod.[4]
______
NOTES